In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of . They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter aleph (ℵ).
The smallest cardinality of an infinite set is that of the , denoted by (read aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null); the next larger cardinality of a well-order set is then then and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define an infinite cardinal number for every ordinal number as described below.
The concept and notation are due to Georg Cantor,
who quotes
who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities.
The aleph numbers differ from the infinity () commonly found in algebra and calculus, in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets, while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the real number line (applied to a function or sequence that "divergent series to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or as an extreme point of the extended real number line.
Among the countably infinite sets are certain infinite ordinals, including for example , , , , , and . For example, the sequence (with order type ) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers is an ordering of the set (with cardinality ) of positive integers.
If the axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the axiom of choice) holds, then is smaller than any other infinite cardinal, and is therefore the (unique) least infinite ordinal.
The definition of implies (in ZF, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between and If the axiom of choice is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered, and thus is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. One can show one of the most useful properties of the set : Any countable subset of has an upper bound in (this follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable). This fact is analogous to the situation in : Every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and finite unions of finite sets are finite.
An example application of the ordinal is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e.g. Borel hierarchy). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (, group theory, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations – sums, products, etc. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible countable unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of
The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the natural numbers and the real numbers.
Notably, is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all : For any natural number , we can consistently assume that , and moreover it is possible to assume that is as least as large as any cardinal number we like. The main restriction ZFC puts on the value of is that it cannot equal certain special cardinals with cofinality . An uncountably infinite cardinal having cofinality means that there is a (countable-length) sequence of cardinals whose limit (i.e. its least upper bound) is (see Easton's theorem). As per the definition above, is the limit of a countable-length sequence of smaller cardinals.
We can then define the aleph numbers as follows:
The -th infinite initial ordinal is written . Its cardinality is written .
Informally, the aleph function is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals.
Formally, in ZFC, is not a function, but a function-like class, as it is not a set (due to the Burali-Forti paradox).
In many cases is strictly greater than α. For example, it is true for any successor Ordinal number: holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence
which is sometimes denoted .
Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function.
Each finite set is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.
Over ZF, the assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.
When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as of minimum possible rank. This has the property that if and only if and have the same cardinality. (The set does not have the same cardinality of in general, but all its elements do.)
Aleph-omega
Aleph-α for general α
Fixed points of omega
Role of axiom of choice
See also
Notes
External links
|
|