Product Code Database
Example Keywords: android -paint $62
barcode-scavenger
   » » Wiki: Aleph Number
Tag Wiki 'Aleph Number'.
Tag

In , particularly in , the aleph numbers are a of numbers used to represent the (or size) of . They were introduced by the mathematician and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter (ℵ).

The smallest cardinality of an infinite set is that of the , denoted by \aleph_0 (read aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null); the next larger cardinality of a set is \aleph_1, then \aleph_2, then \aleph_3, and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define an infinite \aleph_{\alpha} for every \alpha, as described below.

The concept and notation are due to ,

who quotes
     
(1990). 9780691024479, Princeton University Press. .
who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities.

The aleph numbers differ from the infinity (\infty) commonly found in algebra and calculus, in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets, while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the real number line (applied to a function or that " to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or as an extreme point of the extended real number line.


Aleph-zero
\aleph_0 ( aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null) is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is an infinite cardinal. The set of all finite , called \omega or \omega_0 (where \omega is the lowercase Greek letter ), also has cardinality \aleph_0. A set has cardinality \aleph_0 if and only if it is countably infinite, that is, there is a (one-to-one correspondence) between it and the natural numbers. Examples of such sets are

  • the set of , irrespective of including or excluding zero,
  • the set of all ,
  • any infinite subset of the integers, such as the set of all or the set of all ,
  • the set of all ,
  • the set of all constructible numbers (in the geometric sense),
  • the set of all ,
  • the set of all computable numbers,
  • the set of all computable functions,
  • the set of all binary strings of finite length, and
  • the set of all finite of any given countably infinite set.

Among the countably infinite sets are certain infinite ordinals, including for example \omega, \omega+1, \omega \cdot 2, \omega^2, \omega^\omega, and \varepsilon_0. For example, the sequence (with \omega \cdot 2) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers \{1, 3, 5, 7, 9, \cdots; 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, \cdots\} is an ordering of the set (with cardinality \aleph_0) of positive integers.

If the axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the axiom of choice) holds, then \aleph_0 is smaller than any other infinite cardinal, and is therefore the (unique) least infinite ordinal.


Aleph-one
\aleph_1 is the cardinality of the set of all countable . This set is denoted by \omega_1 (or sometimes Ω). The set \omega_1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an . Therefore, \aleph_1 is the smallest cardinality that is larger than \aleph_0, the smallest infinite cardinality.

The definition of \aleph_1 implies (in ZF, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between \aleph_0 and \aleph_1. If the axiom of choice is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is , and thus \aleph_1 is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. One can show one of the most useful properties of the set : Any countable subset of \omega_1 has an upper bound in \omega_1 (this follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable). This fact is analogous to the situation in \aleph_0: Every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and of finite sets are finite.

An example application of the ordinal \omega_1 is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e.g. ). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (, , etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations – sums, products, etc. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible countable unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of \omega_1.


Continuum hypothesis
The of the set of (cardinality of the continuum) is 2\aleph_0. It cannot be determined from (Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory augmented with the axiom of choice) where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy, but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis (CH) is equivalent to the identity
2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_1.

The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the natural numbers and the real numbers.

CH is independent of : It can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that is ). That CH is consistent with was demonstrated by Kurt Gödel in 1940, when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of . That it is independent of was demonstrated by in 1963, when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of – by the (then-novel) method of forcing.


Aleph-omega
Aleph-omega is \aleph_\omega = \sup\{\aleph_n| n \in \omega\} = \sup\{\aleph_n| n \in \{0, 1, 2,\cdots\}\} where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted as \omega. That is, the cardinal number \aleph_\omega is the least upper bound of \sup\{\aleph_n| n \in \{0, 1, 2,\cdots\}\}.

Notably, \aleph_\omega is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all 2^{\aleph_0}: For any natural number n \ge 1 , we can consistently assume that 2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_n, and moreover it is possible to assume that 2^{\aleph_0} is as least as large as any cardinal number we like. The main restriction ZFC puts on the value of 2^{\aleph_0} is that it cannot equal certain special cardinals with \aleph_0. An uncountably infinite cardinal \kappa having cofinality \aleph_0 means that there is a (countable-length) sequence \kappa_0 \le \kappa_1 \le \kappa_2 \le \cdots of cardinals \kappa_i < \kappa whose limit (i.e. its least upper bound) is \kappa (see Easton's theorem). As per the definition above, \aleph_\omega is the limit of a countable-length sequence of smaller cardinals.


Aleph-α for general α
To define \aleph_\alpha for arbitrary ordinal number \alpha, we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number \rho the next larger cardinal \rho^{+} (if the axiom of choice holds, this is the (unique) next larger cardinal).

We can then define the aleph numbers as follows:

\aleph_0 = \omega
\aleph_{\alpha+1} = (\aleph_{\alpha})^{+}
\aleph_{\lambda} = \bigcup\{\aleph_\alpha | \alpha < \lambda\} for \lambda an infinite ,

The \alpha-th infinite is written \omega_\alpha. Its cardinality is written \aleph_\alpha.

Informally, the aleph function \aleph : \text{On} \rightarrow \text{Cd} is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals. Formally, in , \aleph is not a function, but a function-like class, as it is not a set (due to the Burali-Forti paradox).


Fixed points of omega
For any ordinal \alpha we have \alpha \le \omega_\alpha.

In many cases \omega_\alpha is strictly greater than α. For example, it is true for any successor : \alpha + 1 \le \omega_{\alpha + 1} holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence

\omega, \omega_{\omega}, \omega_{\omega_{\omega}}, \cdots

which is sometimes denoted \omega_{\omega_{\ddots}}.

Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function.

This can be shown in ZFC as follows. Suppose \kappa = \aleph_{\lambda} is a weakly inaccessible cardinal. If \lambda were a successor ordinal, then \aleph_{\lambda} would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible. If \lambda were a less than \kappa then its (and thus the cofinality of \aleph_\lambda) would be less than \kappa and so \kappa would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible. Thus \lambda \ge \kappa and consequently \lambda = \kappa which makes it a fixed point.


Role of axiom of choice
The cardinality of any infinite is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its . Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is with an ordinal and is thus .

Each is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.

Over ZF, the assumption that the cardinality of each is an aleph number is equivalent to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.

When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define \text{card}(S) to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank. This has the property that \text{card}(S) = \text{card}(T) if and only if S and T have the same cardinality. (The set \text{card}(S) does not have the same cardinality of S in general, but all its elements do.)


See also


Notes

External links
Page 1 of 1
1
Page 1 of 1
1

Account

Social:
Pages:  ..   .. 
Items:  .. 

Navigation

General: Atom Feed Atom Feed  .. 
Help:  ..   .. 
Category:  ..   .. 
Media:  ..   .. 
Posts:  ..   ..   .. 

Statistics

Page:  .. 
Summary:  .. 
1 Tags
10/10 Page Rank
5 Page Refs